Afternoon Special: Happy Birthday Hans-Hermann Hoppe

by | Sep 2, 2025

Afternoon Special: Happy Birthday Hans-Hermann Hoppe

by | Sep 2, 2025

37587013412 bd9d21b7fa k

Photo Credit: Gage Skidmore

Hans‑Hermann Hoppe, born September 2, 1949, has carved a singular niche in libertarian thought. After earning a doctorate in philosophy in Germany, he moved to the United States in the 1980s to study under economist Murray Rothbard. His books A Theory of Socialism and Capitalism, The Economics and Ethics of Private Property, and Democracy: The God That Failed argue that the modern state is predatory and that a free society rests on private property, voluntary exchange, and decentralized order. In celebrating his seventy‑sixth birthday we can revisit a handful of themes that illustrate why his writings remain both influential and controversial.

Hoppe begins his critique of modern politics by stripping government of its romantic veneer. In a lecture on war and the state he defined the state as “a compulsory territorial monopolist of ultimate decision‑making” and “a territorial monopolist of taxation.” Because it permits no competing courts or tax collectors, such an institution adjudicates disputes in its own favor, turning law from a shield for property into a club for expropriation. Hoppe warns that under these conditions “justice will be perverted in favor of the state.” From this simple institutional insight he proceeds to criticize democracy not for failing to represent the people properly but for aggravating the dangers inherent in monopolized power.

The heart of his argument appears in Democracy: The God That Failed. In monarchies, he contends, the king regards his realm “as individual property which [he seeks] to preserve and enhance” because he expects to pass it on to an heir. A monarch therefore has some incentive to conserve the capital value of his domain. Democratic politicians, by contrast, are “temporary caretakers” who own neither the assets they manage nor the tax stream they extract, so they have every reason to maximize present revenues. Hence his uncompromising conclusion that “Democracy has nothing to do with freedom” and is “a soft variant of communism.” Democracy, in his view, does not tame the state; it turns exploitation into a bidding war in which majorities expropriate minorities.

Hoppe’s critique has resonated with libertarians who see in modern politics an auction of favors at the expense of property owners. Yet his purpose is not to restore kings but to demonstrate that voting rules cannot solve the problem of monopoly. By challenging the identification of democracy with liberty, he forces readers to consider whether political equality and limited government can coexist or whether expanding the franchise simply broadens the ranks of claimants on the public purse.

If politics fails to provide justice, Hoppe proposes a different foundation: self‑ownership and original appropriation. Human beings, he argues, invariably employ scarce means—our bodies, spaces, and physical goods—to pursue their ends. Scarcity makes conflict possible; cooperation requires rules specifying who may control which resources. In a discussion of Rothbardian ethics, Hoppe formulates the principle succinctly: “Everyone is the proper owner of his own physical body as well as of all places and nature‑given goods that he occupies and puts to use…provided only that no one else has already occupied or used the same places and goods before him.” This rule gives each person secure control over his body and the products of his labor and allows unowned goods to be appropriated by the first user. Once acquired, property can be transferred only by consent, not by decree.

Hoppe stresses that these norms are not arbitrary. In a lecture on natural order he notes that because every action employs a scarce resource, “every good [must] be always and at all times owned privately.” Ownership originates through “acts of original appropriation,” establishing a clear link between person and thing, and all legitimate property can be traced back through voluntary transactions to some act of first use. This natural law implies that taxation, regulation, and forcible redistribution are forms of unearned taking. In Hoppe’s view, a legal order grounded in property rights and contract—not legislation or majority vote—would minimize conflict and make coercive institutions obsolete.

Hoppe also tells a story about how political authority emerged from earlier voluntary arrangements. In “Natural Elites, Intellectuals, and the State,” he explains that early societies were governed by natural elites—families or clans whose wealth and reputations earned them respect. These elites acted as judges and arbitrators, applying customary law and often charging nothing for their services, and disputants could choose among various courts with enforcement relying on ostracism, restitution, and reputation. The transition to coercive government occurred when a dominant clan claimed exclusive jurisdiction over conflict resolution. Hoppe describes the resulting institution as an agency that “may engage in continual, institutionalized property rights violations and the exploitation of private property owners through expropriation, taxation, and regulation.”

Statism, Hoppe argues, emerged when a dominant clan claimed exclusive jurisdiction over conflict resolution. One member of the elite, he writes, asserted that “all conflicts within a specified territory be brought before him,” forbidding litigants from seeking alternative judges. Justice thus became monopoly financed by compulsory tribute. Once such a monopoly existed it could add taxation and conscription with little resistance. Hoppe casts the state not as a voluntary covenant but as the institutionalization of conquest and notes that elected rulers inherit the same prerogatives.

Hoppe’s economic analysis focuses on how governments finance their activities. In “Banking, Nation States, and International Politics,” he calls the “monopolization of money and banking…the ultimate pillar on which the modern state rests.” A government that controls money can extract wealth through inflation more easily than through open taxation. Hoppe notes that central banks allow states to expand the money supply “more directly, quickly and securely” than would be possible by raising taxes or selling bonds. Newly created money goes first to the state, banks, and favored industries; only later does the price level rise, eroding the purchasing power of wages and savings. The result is a hidden tax that finances welfare spending, wars, and political patronage while masking the true costs from voters.

For Hoppe, there is no way to democratize such a privilege. The abuse of paper money is a structural feature of monetary monopoly, not a flaw in its management. Consequently he calls for separating money from the state entirely. Commodity money and competitive banking, he argues, would limit inflation, discipline governments, and force politicians to finance programs transparently. His rhetoric is uncompromising: fiat money is not just unsound economics; it is an instrument of domination.

Perhaps no aspect of Hoppe’s work is more controversial than his claim that the state’s most fundamental role—protection from aggression—can be supplied privately. In his essay “The Private Production of Defense,” he rejects the popular belief that collective security requires a territorial monopolist. Modern governments, he writes, justify their existence by claiming that without them “person and property” would be insecure, yet this is “a myth that provides no justification for the modern state.” True security, he contends, arises from the same forces that provide other goods and services: specialization, voluntary cooperation, and competition. As he puts it, “Private‑property owners, cooperation based on the division of labor, and market competition can and should provide defense from aggression.”

Hoppe envisions a network of insurance companies, arbitration agencies, and protection firms that would offer individuals and communities defensive services. Because these providers compete, they have incentives to minimize conflict and respect property rights. Customers dissatisfied with their services can switch to rivals, unlike a state that finances itself through taxation regardless of performance. Hoppe concedes that violence would persist under anarchy but insists that the worst crimes of the twentieth century were perpetrated by states. By stripping government of its monopoly on force, he argues, violence would shrink and defense services would more closely reflect individual preferences.

Hans‑Hermann Hoppe’s influence stems less from academic popularity than from the coherence and audacity of his arguments. By exposing the predatory nature of democratic politics, he forces defenders of the status quo to confront uncomfortable truths about taxation, debt, and war. By grounding rights in self‑ownership and first use, he provides a moral framework for voluntary societies. Through his story of natural elites and the birth of the state, he demystifies political authority and shows it to be a historical accident rather than a necessity. His analysis of money reveals how the power to create currency enables exploitation, and his defense of private security challenges the last refuge of state apologists. These themes, delivered with clarity and conviction, explain why Hoppe’s works remain staples of libertarian reading lists.

As he enters his seventy‑seventh year, Hoppe remains celebrated in libertarian circles for following arguments to their logical conclusion. Critics accuse him of extremism, but his core message is simple: freedom and coercion cannot coexist. By urging us to imagine a world organized around property, contract, and voluntary association, he reminds us that true liberalism requires more than electoral reforms—it requires dismantling monopolies that make exploitation possible. In that sense, his intellectual legacy remains an indelible mark on libertarian thought.

Alan Mosley

Alan Mosley is a historian, jazz musician, policy researcher for the Tenth Amendment Center, and host of It's Too Late, "The #1 Late Night Show in America (NOT hosted by a Communist)!" New episodes debut every Wednesday night at 9ET across all major platforms; just search "AlanMosleyTV" or "It's Too Late with Alan Mosley."

View all posts

Our Books

Shop books published by the Libertarian Institute.

Podcasts

scotthortonshow logosq

coi banner sq2@0.5x

liberty weekly thumbnail

Don't Tread on Anyone Logo

313x0w (1)

313x0w (1)

313x0w (1)

Our Books

Recent Articles

Recent

Pin It on Pinterest

Share This